Frases de Porfirio

Porfirio [1]​ fue un filósofo neoplatónico sirio[2]​[3]​ y discípulo de Plotino. Se encargó de la sistematización y publicación de la obra de Plotino Enéadas y su biografía, Vida de Plotino. Es un temprano expositor de la filosofía del vegetarianismo, como puede verse en su tratado Sobre la abstinencia.



Wikipedia  

✵ 233 – 301
Porfirio Foto
Porfirio: 16   frases 1   Me gusta

Frases célebres de Porfirio

“Aunque todos los lobos y buitres de la tierra se unieran para convencerme de las ventajas de la carne, no por ello dejaría de verlo como un crimen.”

Fuente: Alberto Álvarez, Ariel. Yoga Occidentalis. Editorial Punto Rojo Libros, 2014. ISBN 9781629347998, p. 55.

“Plotino, el filósofo nacido en nuestro tiempo, tenía el aspecto de quien se siente avergonzado de estar en un cuerpo.”

Fuente: Plotino. Enéadas. Ediciones Colihue SRL, 2007. ISBN 978-95-0563-032-5, p. 3.
Fuente: Porfirio, Vida de Plotino 1, 1.9.

“Si se debe justicia a los seres racionales, ¿Como es posible no admitir que estamos asimismo obligados a actuar justamente con para con las especies que están bajo nosotros?”

Fuente: VV. AA. Todos los animales somos hermanos: ensayos sobre el lugar de los animales en las sociedades industrializadas; Volumen 3 de Biblioteca de bolsillo. Editorial Editorial Universidad de Granada, 2003. ISBN 978-84-3383-046-3, p. 480.
Fuente: Libro Todos los animales somos hermanos: ensayos sobre el lugar de los animales en las sociedades industrializadas.

Porfirio: Frases en inglés

“Things essentially incorporeal, because they are more excellent than all body and place, are every where, not with interval, but impartibly.”

2 - 4
Auxiliaries to the Perception of Intelligible Natures
Contexto: Things essentially incorporeal, because they are more excellent than all body and place, are every where, not with interval, but impartibly.
Things essentially incorporeal are not locally present with bodies but are present with them when they please; by verging towards them so far as they are naturally adapted so to verge. They are not, however, present with them locally, but through habitude, proximity, and alliance.
Things essentially incorporeal, are not present with bodies, by hypostasis and essence; for they are not mingled with bodies. But they impart a certain power which is proximate to bodies, through verging towards them. For tendency constitutes a certain secondary power proximate to bodies.

“The soul is bound to the body by a conversion to the corporeal passions; and again liberated by becoming impassive to the body.
That which nature binds, nature also dissolves: and that which the soul binds, the soul likewise dissolves.”

7 - 10
Auxiliaries to the Perception of Intelligible Natures
Contexto: The soul is bound to the body by a conversion to the corporeal passions; and again liberated by becoming impassive to the body.
That which nature binds, nature also dissolves: and that which the soul binds, the soul likewise dissolves. Nature, indeed, bound the body to the soul; but the soul binds herself to the body. Nature, therefore, liberates the body from the soul; but the soul liberates herself from the body.
Hence there is a twofold death; the one, indeed, universally known, in which the body is liberated from the soul; but the other peculiar to philosophers, in which the soul is liberated from the body. Nor does the one entirely follow the other.
We do not understand similarly in all things, but in a manner adapted to the essence of each. For intellectual objects we understand intellectually; but those that pertain to soul rationally. We apprehend plants spermatically; but bodies idolically (i. e., as images); and that which is above all these, super-intellectually and super-essentially.

“Soul, indeed, is a certain medium between an impartible essence, and an essence which is divisible about bodies.”

5 - 6
Auxiliaries to the Perception of Intelligible Natures
Contexto: Soul, indeed, is a certain medium between an impartible essence, and an essence which is divisible about bodies. But intellect is an impartible essence alone. And qualities and material forms are divisible about bodies.
Not everything which acts on another, effects that which it does effect by approximation and contact; but those natures which effect any thing by approximation and contact, use approximation accidentally.

“The utility of a science which enables men to take cognizance of the travellers on the mind's highway, and excludes those disorderly interlopers, verbal fallacies, needs but small attestation.”

Introduction to Aristotle's Organon, as translated by Octavius Freire Owen (1853), p. v
Contexto: The utility of a science which enables men to take cognizance of the travellers on the mind's highway, and excludes those disorderly interlopers, verbal fallacies, needs but small attestation. Its searching penetration by definition alone, before which even mathematical precision fails, would especially commend it to those whom the abstruseness of the study does not terrify, and who recognise the valuable results which must attend discipline of mind. Like a medicine, though not a panacea for every ill, it has the health of the mind for its aim, but requires the determination of a powerful will to imbibe its nauseating yet wholesome influence: it is no wonder therefore that puny intellects, like weak stomachs, abhor and reject it.

Autores similares

Heráclito Foto
Heráclito 48
filósofo presocrático
Epicteto Foto
Epicteto 46
filósofo estoico griego
Sócrates Foto
Sócrates 85
filósofo griego clásico ateniense
Diógenes de Sinope Foto
Diógenes de Sinope 19
filósofo griego
Antístenes Foto
Antístenes 7
filósofo griego
Zenón de Citio Foto
Zenón de Citio 7
filósofo de la antigua Grecia, fundador del estoicismo
Tales de Mileto Foto
Tales de Mileto 35
filósofo y científico
Laocio Foto
Laocio 65
filósofo chino
Epicuro Foto
Epicuro 44
filósofo griego
Pitágoras Foto
Pitágoras 53
filósofo y matemático griego